翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ Jules-Émile Péan
・ Jules-Émile Saintin
・ Jules-Émile Verschaffelt
・ Jules-Émile Zingg
・ Julesburg
・ Julesburg Advocate
・ Julesburg, Colorado
・ Julesburg, Limpopo
・ Julestemninger
・ Julfa
・ Jules Reimerink
・ Jules Remedios Faye
・ Jules Renard
・ Jules Renkin
・ Jules René Bourguignat
Jules Richard
・ Jules Richomme
・ Jules Rimet
・ Jules Robert Auguste
・ Jules Roche
・ Jules Roguin
・ Jules Romain
・ Jules Romains
・ Jules Rossi
・ Jules Rossignol
・ Jules Rossignon
・ Jules Roulleau
・ Jules Roy
・ Jules Rykovich
・ Jules Rémy


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Jules Richard : ウィキペディア英語版
Jules Richard
Jules Richard (born 12 August 1862 in Blet, Département Cher, died 14 October 1956 in Châteauroux, Département Indre) was a French mathematician.
== Life and Works==

Richard taught at the lycées of Tours, Dijon and Châteauroux. He obtained his doctorate, at age of 39, from the Faculté des Sciences in Paris. His thesis of 126 pages concerns Fresnel's wave-surface. Richard worked mainly on the foundations of mathematics and geometry, relating to works by Hilbert, von Staudt and Méray.
In a more philosophical treatise about the nature of axioms of geometry Richard discusses and rejects the following basic principles:
* (1) Geometry is founded on arbitrarily chosen axioms - there are infinitely many equally true geometries.
* (2) Experience provides the axioms of geometry, the basis is experimental, the development deductive.
* (3) The axioms of geometry are definitions (in contrast to (1)).
* (4) Axioms are neither experimental nor arbitrary, they force themselves on us since without them experience is not possible.
The latter approach was essentially that proposed by Kant.
Richard arrived at the result that the notion of identity of two objects and the invariability of an object are too vague and need to be specified more precisely. This should be done by axioms.
*Axioms are propositions, the task of which is to make precise the notion of identity of two objects pre-existing in our mind.
Further according to Richard, it is the aim of science to explain the material universe. And although non-Euclidean geometry had not found any applications (Albert Einstein finished his general theory of relativity only in 1915), Richard already stated clairvoyantly:
*One sees that having admitted the notion of angle, one is free to choose the notion of straight line in such a way that one or another of the three geometries is true.
Richard corresponded with Giuseppe Peano and Henri Poincaré. He became known to more than a small group of specialists by formulating his paradox which was extensively use by Poincaré to attack set theory whereupon the advocates of set theory had to refute these attacks.

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Jules Richard」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.